New user? Register here:
Email Address:
Password:
Retype Password:
First Name:
Last Name:
Existing user? Login here:
Reviews

Free Radicals

Wilson Poon

Rfree-radicals.jpgFree Radicals: The secret anarchy of science 
Michael Brooks 
Profile Books, 320pp

In the popular mind, and probably in the minds of many science graduates, the professional scientist is a cooly detached, supremely rational individual making steady progress in extending human understanding (and therefore control) of the universe by following an algorithm known as ‘the scientific method’. This image is propagated more or less consciously by teachers of science at all levels, and subliminally by the persona projected by professional scientists in public. The ‘scientific method’ enunciated in many an elementary text goes something like this: a hypothesis is formulated, experiments are conducted, and if the data confirm the hypothesis, then hey presto, we have a new scientific finding; but if not, then it’s back to the drawing board. Michael Brooks sets out to debunk this popular portrait of ‘the scientist at work’. 

In my experience, it is not until one gets to do one’s own research that one discovers the secret that science doesn’t quite work in this way. The so-called scientific method is silent on some crucial issues. For a start, it doesn’t tell us where the hypothesis comes from. In a student laboratory exercise, this is supplied by the teacher. But the great unknown does not come served up with ready-made questions to be investigated. Out of the potentially infinite number of possible hypotheses (‘All extraterrestrial planets are made of cheddar’ is one), the fledgling researcher has to learn how to formulate ones that are fruitful and testable in finite time. Alas, there is no algorithm for doing that! 

Then there’s the problem of deciding when there is ‘enough data’ to say that the hypothesis is either ‘proven’ or ‘disproven’. A single piece of datum never clinches the argument; instead, as in most criminal trials, one has to rely on the cumulative weight of evidence. Yet again, there is no algorithm for deciding how much ‘weight’ is enough for going to press. 

Finally, especially in biomedical fields, ethical considerations crop up all the time, and there is certainly no algorithm for deciding between ethically acceptable and unacceptable experiments, or for weighing up risks. 

At these and countless other junctures, the image of a detached, rational scientist following a well-defined ‘scientific method’ is clearly inappropriate. A scientist is a human person, and humans simply do not do anything exclusively by detached ratiocination following clear-cut rules. As in any other human activity, scientists follow hunches and rely on intuition; they often simply go where their passions lead – scientists are usually fiercely committed to the truth of the hypotheses they are testing; and they’d better be, if they are to have the persistence required to push through arduous investigations. In the heat of the moment, corners are sometimes cut, leaving holes in the reasoning to be filled in later, if at all. Real science is a messy business, as is anything else done by real humans. The surprising thing is that something approximating to the truth usually emerges from this untidy process.

That this is so has been said before. Famously, the philosopher Paul Feyerabend set the cat among pigeons in 1975 by his book Against Method, arguing that science proceeded much more anarchically than the textbook description of ‘the scientific method’ would allow.  Earlier, in the late 60s, the Nobel medical laureate Sir Peter Medawar had confessed to the same awful secret as an insider. Going back another decade, the distinguished physical chemist turned philosopher Michael Polanyi discussed why and how science was a form of ‘personal knowledge’ in a 1958 classic with that title. Michael Brooks’ book fits into this tradition, although as one might expect from a consultant for the popular magazine New Scientist, this volume is in a far racier style than any of its predecessors. Through well-chosen case studies, Brooks documents the human face of science. There is, as others have argued before, no such thing as a single, coolly detached, scientific method. Instead, scientists would stop at almost nothing to make discoveries, and to get the credit for doing so. 

The term ‘anarchy’ in the subtitle is clearly an echo of Feyerabend. It is a ‘secret’ because it seems that many scientists do not want this state of affairs to become widely known. Brooks relates how Feyerabend was lampooned for being ‘anti-science’ after his book came out. He also tells us that when James Watson, the co-discoverer of the DNA double helix, published an autobiography revealing the same kind of messiness in his scientific career, his fellow Nobel laureates (Crick and Wilkins) were furious, apparently because they thought it a betrayal for a fellow scientist to give away such dirty secrets.

Here is precisely where Brooks is at his strongest and most distinctive. He argues towards the end of Free Radicals that it is vital that the messy humanness of the scientific enterprise should not be kept secret, but should be widely disseminated and appreciated. Science is simply too important in our modern world for us to put its practitioners on a rationalistic pedestal. If we do so, then every time the veil is pulled back slightly (willing or unwilling) to reveal the underlying messiness, there is the danger of an anti-science backlash: ‘Gosh! Scientists are human like us after all, so we can never trust them again!’ Brooks argues that it is not until the ‘secret anarchy of science’ becomes common knowledge that science can truly take the place it deserves in our culture and in public life. I agree.

The book is mostly well written and entertaining. The quality of the non-technical explanations of the science associated with the case studies is admirable. I do worry that at several points in the book, Brooks labels the real methods followed by scientists as ‘irrational’. Moreover, it is a pity that an author who has so successfully shattered one myth should spill significant ink perpetuating another – the supposed necessary conflict between science and religion. Brooks repeatedly talks of the ‘irrationality’ of religion. It is true that the way real science proceeds, and the way religion operates, very often does not fit into the rationality of some supposed ‘scientific method’. But that surely does not render either of these ‘irrational’. It’s just that we have to widen our definition of rationality. And that surely is the enduring message of this book. 

 

Leave a comment